Articoli correlati a An Introduction to Mathematical Analysis for Economic...

An Introduction to Mathematical Analysis for Economic Theory and Econometrics - Rilegato

 
9780691118673: An Introduction to Mathematical Analysis for Economic Theory and Econometrics

Sinossi

Providing an introduction to mathematical analysis as it applies to economic theory and econometrics, this book bridges the gap that has separated the teaching of basic mathematics for economics and the increasingly advanced mathematics demanded in economics research today. Dean Corbae, Maxwell B. Stinchcombe, and Juraj Zeman equip students with the knowledge of real and functional analysis and measure theory they need to read and do research in economic and econometric theory.


Unlike other mathematics textbooks for economics, An Introduction to Mathematical Analysis for Economic Theory and Econometrics takes a unified approach to understanding basic and advanced spaces through the application of the Metric Completion Theorem. This is the concept by which, for example, the real numbers complete the rational numbers and measure spaces complete fields of measurable sets. Another of the book's unique features is its concentration on the mathematical foundations of econometrics. To illustrate difficult concepts, the authors use simple examples drawn from economic theory and econometrics.


Accessible and rigorous, the book is self-contained, providing proofs of theorems and assuming only an undergraduate background in calculus and linear algebra.


  • Begins with mathematical analysis and economic examples accessible to advanced undergraduates in order to build intuition for more complex analysis used by graduate students and researchers

  • Takes a unified approach to understanding basic and advanced spaces of numbers through application of the Metric Completion Theorem

  • Focuses on examples from econometrics to explain topics in measure theory

Le informazioni nella sezione "Riassunto" possono far riferimento a edizioni diverse di questo titolo.

Informazioni sull?autore

Dean Corbae is the Rex A. and Dorothy B. Sebastian Centennial Professor in Business Administration at the University of Texas at Austin. Maxwell B. Stinchcombe is the E. C. McCarty Centennial Professor of Economics at the University of Texas at Austin. Juraj Zeman is researcher at the National Bank of Slovakia and lecturer in applied mathematics at Comenius University in Bratislava.

Dalla quarta di copertina

"I've struggled in teaching a math for economics course for several years without an appropriate text. This book will remedy this problem and, more generally, will fill a gap that has existed in the profession for at least a decade."--L. Joe Moffitt, University of Massachusetts

"This book will prove extremely useful for anyone who wants to learn mathematical economics in an accessible and intuitive fashion, while still tackling advanced concepts. The range of topics is impressive, with many illuminating examples. An excellent text!"--Jaksa Cvitanic, California Institute of Technology

"This book makes accessible an extraordinary amount of mathematics used in economics and carries it to a high level. By means of illustrative examples, the authors succeed in explaining most of the main ideas of economic theory. This is an important resource for economists and an excellent text for mathematics courses for economic graduate students."--Truman F. Bewley, Yale University

"A much-needed textbook for graduate students and a useful desk reference for researchers, this book is of tremendous value to the economics profession because it bridges abstract mathematics and concrete economic applications. Given the current technical level required in research, knowledge of materials covered in this book is indispensable for graduate students."--Han Hong, Stanford University

"Without ever sacrificing rigor, the authors have a style that will help students trying to decipher arcane mathematical ideas. I recommend this book to students."--Richard P. McLean, Rutgers University

Dal risvolto di copertina interno

"I've struggled in teaching a math for economics course for several years without an appropriate text. This book will remedy this problem and, more generally, will fill a gap that has existed in the profession for at least a decade."--L. Joe Moffitt, University of Massachusetts

"This book will prove extremely useful for anyone who wants to learn mathematical economics in an accessible and intuitive fashion, while still tackling advanced concepts. The range of topics is impressive, with many illuminating examples. An excellent text!"--Jaksa Cvitanic, California Institute of Technology

"This book makes accessible an extraordinary amount of mathematics used in economics and carries it to a high level. By means of illustrative examples, the authors succeed in explaining most of the main ideas of economic theory. This is an important resource for economists and an excellent text for mathematics courses for economic graduate students."--Truman F. Bewley, Yale University

"A much-needed textbook for graduate students and a useful desk reference for researchers, this book is of tremendous value to the economics profession because it bridges abstract mathematics and concrete economic applications. Given the current technical level required in research, knowledge of materials covered in this book is indispensable for graduate students."--Han Hong, Stanford University

"Without ever sacrificing rigor, the authors have a style that will help students trying to decipher arcane mathematical ideas. I recommend this book to students."--Richard P. McLean, Rutgers University

Estratto. © Ristampato con autorizzazione. Tutti i diritti riservati.

AN INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS FOR ECONOMIC THEORY AND ECONOMETRICS

By Dean Corbae Maxwell B. Stinchcombe Juraj Zeman

PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS

Copyright © 2009 Princeton University Press
All right reserved.

ISBN: 978-0-691-11867-3

Contents

Preface...............................................................................................................xiUser's Guide..........................................................................................................xiiiNotation..............................................................................................................xixChapter 1 * Logic.....................................................................................................1Chapter 2 * Set Theory................................................................................................15Chapter 3 * The Space of Real Numbers.................................................................................72Chapter 4 * The Finite-Dimensional Metric Space of Real Vectors.......................................................106Chapter 5 * Finite-Dimensional Convex Analysis........................................................................172Chapter 6 * Metric Spaces.............................................................................................259Chapter 7 * Measure Spaces and Probability............................................................................355Chapter 8 * The Lp(Ω, F, P) and lp Spaces, p [member of] [1, ∞].....................452Chapter 9 * Probabilities on Metric Spaces............................................................................551Chapter 10 * Infinite-Dimensional Convex Analysis.....................................................................595Chapter 11 * Expanded Spaces..........................................................................................627Index.................................................................................................................655

Chapter One

Logic

The building blocks of modern economics are based on logical reasoning to prove the validity of a conclusion, B, from well-defined premises, A. In general, statements such as A and/or B can be represented using sets, and a "proof" is constructed by applying, sometimes ingeniously, a fixed set of rules to establish that the statement B is true whenever A is true. We begin with examples of how we represent statements as sets, then turn to the rules that allow us to form more and more complex statements, and then give a taxonomy of the major types of proofs that we use in this book.

1.1 * Statements, Sets, Subsets, and Implication

The idea of a set (of things), or group, or collection is a "primitive," one that we use without being able to clearly define it. The idea of belonging to a set (group, collection) is primitive in exactly the same sense. Our first step is to give the allowable rules by which we evaluate whether statements about sets are true.

We begin by fixing a set X of things that we might have an interest in. When talking about demand behavior, the set X has to include, at the very least, prices, incomes, affordable consumption sets, preference relations, and preference-optimal sets. The set X varies with the context, and is often not mentioned at all.

We express the primitive notion of membership by "[member of]," so that "x [member of] A" means that "x is an element of the set A" and "y [not member of] A" means that "y is not an element of A."

Notation Alert 1.1.A Capitalized letters are usually reserved for sets and smaller letters for points/things in the set that we are studying. Sometimes, several levels of analysis are present simultaneously, and we cannot do this. Consider the study of utility functions, u, on a set of options, X. A function u is a set of pairs of the form (x, u(x)), with x an option and u(x) the number representing its utility. However, in our study of demand behavior, we want to see what happens as u varies. From this perspective, u is a point in the set of possible utility functions.

Membership allows us to define subsets. We say "A is a subset of B," written "A [subset] B," if every x [member of] A satisfies x [member of] B. Thus, subsets are defined in terms of the primitive relation "[member of]." We write A = B if A [subset] B and B [subset] A, and A [not equal to] B otherwise.

We usually specify the elements of a set explicitly by saying "The set A is the set of all elements x in X such that each x has the property A, that is, that A(x) is true," and write "A = {x [member of] X : A(x)}" as a shorter version of this. For example, with X = Rl, the statement "x ≥ 0" is identified with the set Rl+ = {x [member of] X : x ≥ 0}. In this way, we identify a statement with the set of elements of X for which the statement is true. There are deep issues in logic and the foundations of mathematics relating to the question of whether or not all sets can be identified by "properties." Fortunately, these issues rarely impinge on the mathematics that economists need. Chapter 2 is more explicit about these issues.

We are very often interested in establishing the truth of statements of the form "If A, then B." There are many equivalent ways of writing such a statement: "A -> B," "A implies B," "A only if B," "A is sufficient for B," or "B is necessary for A." To remember the sufficiency and necessity, it may help to subvocalize them as "A is sufficiently strong to guarantee B" and "B is necessarily true if A is true."

The logical relation of implication is a subset relation. If A = {x [member of] X : A(x)} and B = {x [member of] X :B(x)}, then "A -> B" is the same as "A [subset] B."

Example 1.1.1 Let X be the set of numbers, A(x) the statement "x2 < 1," and B(x) the statement "|x| ≤ 1." Now, A -> B. In terms of sets, A = {x [member of] X :A(x)} is the set of numbers strictly between -1 and +1, B = {x [member of] X :B(x)} is the set of numbers greater than or equal to -1 and less than or equal to +1, and A [subset] B.

The statements of interest can be quite complex to write out in their entirety. If X is the set of allocations in a model E of an economy and A(x) is the statement "x is a Walrasian equilibrium allocated for the economy ε," then a complete specification of the statement takes a great deal of work. Presuming some familiarity with general equilibrium models, we offer the following.

Example 1.1.2 Let X be the set of allocations in a model ε of an economy; let A(x) be the statement "x is a Walrasian equilibrium allocation"; and B(x) be the statement "x is Pareto efficient for ε." The first fundamental theorem of welfare economics is A -> B. In terms of the definition of subsets, this is expressed as, "Every Walrasian equilibrium allocation is Pareto efficient."

In other cases, we are interested in the truth of statements of the form "A if and only if B," often written "A iff B." Equivalently, such a statement can be written: "A -> B and B -> A," which is often shortened to "A <-> B." Other frequently used formulations are: "A implies B and B implies A," "A is necessary and sufficient for B," or "A is equivalent to B." In terms of the corresponding sets A and B, these are all different ways of writing "A = B."

Example 1.1.3 Let X be the set of numbers, A(x) the statement "0 ≤ x ≤ 1," and B(x) the statement "x2x." From high school algebra, A <-> B. In terms of sets, A = {x [member of] X :A(x)} and B = {x [member of] X : B(x)} are both the sets of numbers greater than or equal to 0 and less than or equal to 1.

1.2 * Statements and Their Truth Values

Note that a statement of the form "A -> B" is simply a construct of two simple statements connected by "->." This is one of seven ways of constructing new statements that we use. In this section, we cover the first five of them: ands, ors, nots, implies, and equivalence. Repeated applications of these seven ways of constructing statements yield more and more elaboration and complication.

We begin with the simplest three methods, which construct new sets directly from a set or pair of sets that we start with. We then turn to the statements that are about relations between sets and introduce another formulation in terms of indicator functions. Later we give the other two methods, which involve the logical quantifiers "for all" and "there exists." Throughout, interest focuses on methods of establishing the truth or falsity of statements, that is, on methods of proof.

1.2.a Ands/Ors/Nots as Intersections/Unions/Complements

The simplest three ways of constructing new statements from other ones are using the connectives "and" or "or," or by "not," which is negation. Notationally: "A [conjunction] B" means "A and B," "A [disjunction] B" means "A or B," and "[logical not] A" means "not A."

In terms of the corresponding sets: "A [conjunction] B" is A [intersection] B, the intersection of A and B, that is, the set of all points that belong to both A and B; "A [disjunction] B" is A [union] B, the union of A and B, that is, the set of all points that belong to A or belong to B; and "[logical not] A" is Ac = {x [member of] X : x [not member of] A}, the complement of A, is the set of all elements of X that do not belong to A.

The meanings of these new statements, [logical not] A, A [conjunction] B, and A [disjunction] B, are given by a truth table, Table 1.a. The corresponding Table 1.b gives the corresponding set versions of the new statements.

The first two columns of Table 1.a give possible truth values for the statements A and B. The last three columns give the truth values for [logical not] A, A [conjunction] B, and A [disjunction] B as a function of the truth values of A and B. The first two columns of Table 1.b give the corresponding membership properties of an element x, and the last three columns give the corresponding membership properties of x in the sets Ac, A [intersection] B, and A [union] B.

Consider the second rows of both tables, the row where A is true and B is false. This corresponds to discussing an x with the properties that it belongs to A and does not belong to B. The statement "not A," that is, [logical not] A, is false, which corresponds to x not belonging to Ac, x [not member of] Ac. The statement "A and B," that is, "A [conjunction] B," is also false. This is sensible: since B is false, it is not the case that both A and B are true. This corresponds to x not being in the intersection of A and B, that is, x [not member of] A [intersection] B. The statement "A or B," that is, "A [disjunction] B," is true. This is sensible: since A is true, it is the case that at least one of A and B is true, corresponding to x being in the union of A and B.

It is important to note that we use the word "or" in its nonexclusive sense. When we describe someone as "tall or red-headed," we mean to allow tall red-headed people. We do not mean "or" in the exclusive sense that the person is either tall or red-headed but not both. One sees this by considering the last columns in the two tables, the ones with the patterns TTTF and [member of][member of][member of][not member of]. "A or B" is true as long as at least one of A and B is true, and we do not exclude the possibility that both are true. The exclusive "or" is defined by (A [disjunction] B) [conjunction] ([logical not] (A [conjunction] B)c, which has the truth pattern FTTF. In terms of sets, the exclusive "or" is (A [union] B) [intersection] (A [intersection] B)c, which has the corresponding membership pattern [not member of][member of][member of][not member of].

1.2.b Implies/Equivalence as Subset/Equality

Two of the remaining four ways of constructing new statements are: "A -> B," which means "A implies B" and "A <-> B," which means "A is equivalent to B." In terms of sets, these are "A [subset] B" and "A = B." These are statements about relations between subsets of X.

Indicator functions are a very useful way to talk about the relations between subsets. For each x [member of] X and A [subset] X, define the indicator of the set A by

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (1.1)

Remember, a proposition, A, is a statement about elements x [member of] X that can be either true or false. When it is true, we write A(x). The corresponding set A is {x [member of] X : A(x)}. The indicator of A takes on the value 1 for exactly those x for which A is true and takes on the value 0 for those x for which A is false.

Indicator functions are ordered pointwise; that is, 1A ≤ 1B when 1A(x) ≤ 1B(x) for every point x in the set X. Saying "1A ≤ 1B" is the same as saying that "A [subset] B." It is easy to give sets A and B that satisfy neither A [subset] B nor B [subset] A. Therefore, unlike pairs of numbers r and s, for which it is always true that either rs or sr, pairs of indicator functions may not be ranked by "≤."

Example 1.2.1 If X is the three-point set {a, b, c}, A = {a, b}, B = {b, c}, and C = {c}, then 1A ≤ 1X, 1B = 1X, 1C = 1B, ?(1A = 1B), and ?(1B = 1A).

Proving statements of the form A -> B and A <-> B is the essential part of mathematical reasoning. For the first, we take the truth of A as given and then establish logically that the truth of B follows. For the second, we take the additional step of taking the truth of B as given and then establish logically that the truth of A follows. In terms of sets, for proving the first, we take a point, x, assume only that x [member of] A, and establish that this implies that x [member of] B, thus proving that A [subset] B. For proving the second, we take the additional step of taking a point, x, assume only that x [member of] B, and establish that this implies that x [member of] A. Here is the truth table for? and?, both for statements and for indicator functions.

1.2.c The Empty Set and Vacuously True Statements

We now come to the idea of something that is vacuously true, and a substantial proportion of people find this idea tricky or annoying, or both. The idea that we are after is that starting from false premises, one can establish anything. In Table 1.c, if A is false, then the statement A -> B is true, whether B is true or false.

A statement that is false for all x [member of] X corresponds to having an indicator function with the property that for all x [member of] X, 1A(x) = 0. In terms of sets, the notation for this is A = [empty set], where we read "[empty set]" as the empty set, that is, the vacuous set, the one that contains no elements. No matter what the set B is, if A = [empty set], then 1A(x) ≤ 1B(x) for all x [member of] X.

Definition 1.2.2 The statement A -> B is vacuously true if A = [empty set]. This definition follows the convention that we use throughout: we show the term or terms being defined in boldface type.

In terms of sets, this is the observation that for all B, [empty set] B, that is, that every element of [empty set] belongs to B. What many people find distasteful is that "every element of [empty set] belongs to B" suggests that there is an element of [empty set], and since there is no such element, the statement feels wrong to them. There is nothing to be done except to get over the feeling.

1.2.d Indicators and Ands/Ors/Nots

Indicator functions can also be used to capture ands, ors, and nots. Often this makes proofs simpler.

The pointwise minimum of a pair of indicator functions, 1A and 1B, is written as "1A [conjunction] 1B," and is defined by (1A [conjunction] 1B)(x) = min{1A(x), 1B(x)}. Now, 1A(x) and 1B(x) are equal either to 0 or to 1. Since the minimum of 1 and 1 is 1, the minimum of 0 and 1 is 0, and the minimum of 0 and 0 is 0, 1A [intersection] B = 1A [conjunction] 1B. This means that the indicator associated with the statement "A ? B" is 1A ? 1B. By checking cases, we note that for all x [member of] X, (1A [conjunction] 1B(x) = 1A(x) x 1B(x). As a result, 1A [conjunction] 1B is often written as 1A x 1B.

(Continues...)


Excerpted from AN INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS FOR ECONOMIC THEORY AND ECONOMETRICSby Dean Corbae Maxwell B. Stinchcombe Juraj Zeman Copyright © 2009 by Princeton University Press. Excerpted by permission of PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS. All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Le informazioni nella sezione "Su questo libro" possono far riferimento a edizioni diverse di questo titolo.

Compra usato

Condizioni: buono
This is an ex-library book and...
Visualizza questo articolo

EUR 11,05 per la spedizione da Regno Unito a Italia

Destinazione, tempi e costi

GRATIS per la spedizione da U.S.A. a Italia

Destinazione, tempi e costi

Risultati della ricerca per An Introduction to Mathematical Analysis for Economic...

Foto dell'editore

Corbae, Dean
ISBN 10: 0691118671 ISBN 13: 9780691118673
Antico o usato Rilegato

Da: Anybook.com, Lincoln, Regno Unito

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

Condizione: Good. This is an ex-library book and may have the usual library/used-book markings inside.This book has hardback covers. In good all round condition. Library sticker on front cover. Please note the Image in this listing is a stock photo and may not match the covers of the actual item,1650grams, ISBN:9780691118673. Codice articolo 5596295

Contatta il venditore

Compra usato

EUR 47,64
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 11,05
Da: Regno Unito a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: 1 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Foto dell'editore

Corbae, Dean, Zeman, Juraj, Stinchcombe, Maxwell
ISBN 10: 0691118671 ISBN 13: 9780691118673
Antico o usato Rilegato

Da: Better World Books, Mishawaka, IN, U.S.A.

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

Condizione: Very Good. Used book that is in excellent condition. May show signs of wear or have minor defects. Codice articolo 4978938-6

Contatta il venditore

Compra usato

EUR 40,10
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 19,91
Da: U.S.A. a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: 1 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Immagini fornite dal venditore

Corbae, Dean; Stinchcombe, Maxwell B.; Zeman, Juraj
ISBN 10: 0691118671 ISBN 13: 9780691118673
Antico o usato Rilegato

Da: PsychoBabel & Skoob Books, Didcot, Regno Unito

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

Hardcover. Condizione: Very Good. Hardcover with printed boards, no dust jacket. Very slight shelfwear to boards, otherwise like new condition. AD. Used. Codice articolo 531130

Contatta il venditore

Compra usato

EUR 51,21
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 34,69
Da: Regno Unito a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: 1 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Foto dell'editore

Dean Corbae; Maxwell B. Stinchcombe; Juraj Zeman
ISBN 10: 0691118671 ISBN 13: 9780691118673
Antico o usato Rilegato

Da: BooksRun, Philadelphia, PA, U.S.A.

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

Hardcover. Condizione: Good. Ship within 24hrs. Satisfaction 100% guaranteed. APO/FPO addresses supported. Codice articolo 0691118671-11-1

Contatta il venditore

Compra usato

EUR 30,69
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 64,51
Da: U.S.A. a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: 1 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Foto dell'editore

Dean Corbae
ISBN 10: 0691118671 ISBN 13: 9780691118673
Nuovo Rilegato

Da: PBShop.store US, Wood Dale, IL, U.S.A.

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

HRD. Condizione: New. New Book. Shipped from UK. Established seller since 2000. Codice articolo WP-9780691118673

Contatta il venditore

Compra nuovo

EUR 98,21
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: GRATIS
Da: U.S.A. a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: 5 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Foto dell'editore

Dean Corbae
ISBN 10: 0691118671 ISBN 13: 9780691118673
Nuovo Rilegato

Da: Kennys Bookshop and Art Galleries Ltd., Galway, GY, Irlanda

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

Condizione: New. 2009. Hardcover. Presents an understanding of basic and advanced spaces through the application of the Metric Completion Theorem. This book focuses on examples from econometrics to explain topics in measure theory. Num Pages: 688 pages, 55 line illus. BIC Classification: KC; PBK. Category: (UU) Undergraduate. Dimension: 254 x 185 x 50. Weight in Grams: 1596. . . . . . Codice articolo V9780691118673

Contatta il venditore

Compra nuovo

EUR 98,86
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 2,00
Da: Irlanda a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: 1 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Immagini fornite dal venditore

Corbae, Dean; Stinchcombe, Maxwell B.; Zeman, Juraj
ISBN 10: 0691118671 ISBN 13: 9780691118673
Nuovo Rilegato

Da: GreatBookPrices, Columbia, MD, U.S.A.

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

Condizione: New. Codice articolo 2576075-n

Contatta il venditore

Compra nuovo

EUR 95,86
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 17,19
Da: U.S.A. a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: 9 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Immagini fornite dal venditore

Corbae, Dean; Stinchcombe, Maxwell B.; Zeman, Juraj
ISBN 10: 0691118671 ISBN 13: 9780691118673
Nuovo Rilegato

Da: GreatBookPricesUK, Woodford Green, Regno Unito

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

Condizione: New. Codice articolo 2576075-n

Contatta il venditore

Compra nuovo

EUR 101,10
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 17,34
Da: Regno Unito a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: 5 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Foto dell'editore

Dean Corbae; Maxwell B. Stinchcombe; Juraj Zeman
ISBN 10: 0691118671 ISBN 13: 9780691118673
Nuovo Rilegato

Da: Ria Christie Collections, Uxbridge, Regno Unito

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

Condizione: New. In. Codice articolo ria9780691118673_new

Contatta il venditore

Compra nuovo

EUR 109,14
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 10,40
Da: Regno Unito a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: 3 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Foto dell'editore

Dean Corbae
ISBN 10: 0691118671 ISBN 13: 9780691118673
Nuovo Rilegato

Da: PBShop.store UK, Fairford, GLOS, Regno Unito

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

HRD. Condizione: New. New Book. Shipped from UK. Established seller since 2000. Codice articolo WP-9780691118673

Contatta il venditore

Compra nuovo

EUR 113,10
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 7,34
Da: Regno Unito a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: 3 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Vedi altre 16 copie di questo libro

Vedi tutti i risultati per questo libro