Articoli correlati a The New Demons: Rethinking Power and Evil Today

The New Demons: Rethinking Power and Evil Today - Brossura

 
9780804792950: The New Demons: Rethinking Power and Evil Today

Sinossi

As long as we care about suffering in the world, says political philosopher Simona Forti, we are compelled to inquire into the question of evil. But is the concept of evil still useful in a postmodern landscape where absolute values have been leveled and relativized by a historicist perspective? Given our current unwillingness to judge others, what signposts remain to guide our ethical behavior?

Surveying the nineteenth- and twentieth-century Western philosophical debates on evil, Forti concludes that it is time to leave behind what she calls "the Dostoevsky paradigm": the dualistic vision of an omnipotent monster pitted against absolute, helpless victims. No longer capable of grasping the normalization of evil in today's world—whose structures of power have been transformed—this paradigm has exhausted its explanatory force.

In its place, Forti offers a different genealogy of the relationship between evil and power, one that finally calls into question power's recurrent link to transgression. At the center of contemporary evil she posits the passive attitude towards rule-following, the need for normalcy, and the desire for obedience nurtured by our contemporary mass democracies. In our times, she contends, evil must be explored in tandem with our stubborn desire to stay alive at all costs as much as with our deep need for recognition: the new modern absolutes. A courageous book, New Demons extends an original, inspiring call to ethical living in a biopolitical age.

Le informazioni nella sezione "Riassunto" possono far riferimento a edizioni diverse di questo titolo.

Informazioni sugli autori

Simona Forti is Professor of Political Philosophy at the University of Piemonte Orientale in Italy.


Simona Forti is Professor of Political Philosophy at the University of Piemonte Orientale in Italy.

Estratto. © Ristampato con autorizzazione. Tutti i diritti riservati.

New Demons

Rethinking Power and Evil Today

By Simona Forti, Zakiya Hanafi

STANFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS

Copyright © 2012 Giangiacomo Feltrinelli Editore
All rights reserved.
ISBN: 978-0-8047-9295-0

Contents

Acknowledgments,
Introduction,
PART I. ABSOLUTE DEMONS: THE POWER OF NOTHINGNESS,
1. The Dostoevsky Paradigm,
2. Instincts, Drives, and Their Vicissitudes: Nietzsche and Freud,
3. Ontological Evil and the Transcendence of Evil,
INTERLUDE: HYPERMORAL BIOPOLITICS,
4. Thanatopolitics and Absolute Victims,
PART II. MEDIOCRE DEMONS: TOWARD A NEW PARADIGM,
5. The Legend of the Grand Inquisitor Reinterpreted from Below,
6. A Different Genealogy: The Evil of Docility,
7. Strategies of Obedience and the Ethos of Freedom,
8. Parrhesia Put to the Test: Practices of Dissidence Between Eastern and Western Europe,
9. Poor Devils Who "Worship" Life: Us,
Notes,
Index of Names,


CHAPTER 1

The Dostoevsky Paradigm


Stavrogin's Ghost

He was a very handsome young man, about twenty-five years old, and I confess I found him striking. I expected to see some dirty ragamuffin, wasted away from depravity and stinking of vodka. On the contrary, this was the most elegant gentleman of any I had ever happened to meet[....] I was also struck by his face: his hair was somehow too black, his light eyes were somehow too calm and clear, his complexion was somehow too delicate and white, his color somehow too bright and clean, his teeth like pearls, his lips like coral—the very image of beauty, it would seem, and at the same time repulsive, as it were.


The analogy that Dostoevsky implicitly suggests in this presentation is difficult to miss. The resemblance between Stavrogin and Lucifer is only too obvious. Like the highest fallen angel, Stavrogin is endowed with all the contrasting qualities that make him not only the greatest of the damned, but also the most magnificent. Dazzling and statuesque, even his beauty hides the power of a demonic charm that attracts and repels at the same time. Too full of himself to love anyone else, too smart to be a fanatic, too disillusioned not to be aware of his own faults, everything about him is hallmarked by excess. And, as many Dostoevsky critics have suggested, with Stavrogin what barges in is more than just the most disturbing protagonist of the novel. Along with him comes the ghost of the next century: the specter of nihilism makes its appearance, in all its multiple facets. In Dostoevsky's view, nihilism was the last era of humanity when Nothingness insinuated itself into history to take the place of God, whose place had already been usurped by man, deified in his turn by positivist optimism.

With this young man who grew up without roots, with no father and no fatherland, the writer dramatizes the extreme consequences of what he saw as the ultimate fate stemming from the loss of meaning. Conceived by Dostoevsky as the main character of the novel, he is the point toward which all the other characters converge and, at the same time, the hub from which the force of negation radiates out along all its possible trajectories. His reason has gone beyond all bounds and touched on nothingness; his senses have run the gamut of excesses and plumbed the void. Stavrogin is not, therefore, simply a well-crafted synthesis of Dostoevsky's remarkable psychological acuity. The writer's intention is much more ambitious: to condense a philosophical vision into a credible phenomenology of the human subject. Indeed, he already knows what Nietzsche would later make clear: nihilism goes far beyond the suppression of traditional moral values and their religious foundation. For this reason, Dostoevsky's writing also seeks to come to terms with the ontological rupture that has imprinted itself on the human realm and history. Beginning with Notes from Underground (whose protagonist he develops and puts into action as Stavrogin), all of Dostoevsky's characters bear the signs of a "revolution of the spirit."

Now, this is not to take sides in the age-old debate on the philosophical status of the work of Fyodor Dostoevsky: that is, whether it represents, for philosophy as well, the final victory of a profound, authentic form of Christianity over the persistence of sin and guilt; or whether his work is instead perpetually dominated by an irrevocably tragic vision. Nor am I interested in taking sides for or against those who, from Lev Shestov to Sergio Givone, through the masterful interpretation of Luigi Pareyson, see the Russian author as the great thinker who anticipated Nietzsche, in some ways even "bypassing him" and successfully avoiding Heidegger's deviations. It suffices to recall in this connection that the young Georg Lukács had already noted "the smallness of Nietzsche" compared to the stature of Stavrogin. What the Hungarian critic saw in this character, and in Demons generally, was a decisive step without which the West would never have gained full self-awareness. All this is to say that there are many influential thinkers who have shared, and continue to share, the emphatic view expressed by Nicolas Berdyaev: "We now philosophize about the last things under the aegis of Dostoevsky. Philosophizing about the next-to-last things alone is the task of traditional philosophy."

But even leaving these questions open for discussion, without getting caught up in the interpretative conundrums about Dostoevsky's work that challenge its most philosophically demanding readers, there is no doubt that it marks a crucial change. Precisely for this reason, I think it legitimate to transpose the literary fictions that it has given voice to into philosophical categories, categories that, I believe, helped to reformulate the question of evil in European culture by linking it in two ways to the problem of nihilism. Going well beyond the traditional conception of the doctrine of original sin, Dostoevsky's radical position not only made an impact on ethics and religion, it also "ontologically" tied together evil and nothingness, freedom and will, into a single node. This is why "Stavrogin's ghost," pars pro toto, continued to waft around philosophy for a long time. Even today, it continues to inspire evocative, albeit impressionistic, interpretations of Islamic terrorism in the vein of Demons.

In the second part of this book, I will explain why we need to let go of the one-sidedness of this approach in order to understand our present times; why, as a hermeneutic lens, in some ways it is still too dependent on a theological vision of the relationship between evil and freedom. For now, however, let us stick to one of its truths that can hardly be disputed: the figures that allowed philosophy, from Nietzsche on, to venture into the unexplored territory of evil took form from Nikolai Vsevolodovich Stavrogin, his thoughts, his actions, and his "friends." When expressed as concepts, these figures formed the horizon in which much of the philosophical culture of the twentieth century believed it could reveal something about the idea of evil in its connection with power that the earlier tradition had passed over. For this reason I believe that we can talk quite confidently of a genuine Dostoevsky paradigm: that is, an arrangement of concepts, a relation between categories, aligned according to a clear nexus, that for a long time was established as a condition of conceivability for evil—though never directly and explicitly. It is a paradigm that Nietzsche and Freud participated in no less than Heidegger, although in different ways: these are the thinkers who, more than anyone else, marked a contemporary turning point in a possible genealogical history of the idea of evil. But, to be more accurate, we should say that only specific aspects of the thought of Nietzsche, Freud, and Heidegger are pertinent to this paradigm, because, as we shall see, I am convinced that there often opens up an alternative perspective from their writings from which to view the question.

Let us start, then, by asking: What does Stavrogin personify? What is he emblematic of, along with Stepan and Pyotr Verkhovensky, Kirillov, and Shatov? But also, what about the three Brothers Karamazov, who are so glaringly "livid" in comparison to the disarming "glow" of Alyosha—what do they tell us? What are we to make of all these demons? What philosophical understanding are we led to by their lives, which even today represent one of the most monumental phenomenologies of evil? First of all, the expressive power of their roles dug up the ground in which the traditional philosophical and theological concepts had been rooted. Their characters played an exemplary, paradigmatic role. But although they have a name and a surname and their individuality is deeply anchored in the narrative context, the moment their complete uniqueness is expressed, a human typology becomes visible that can be transposed into a theoretical matrix. Each character corresponds to a mode of being that evil may assume, fitting together to form a complex phenomenology that can be broken down into its separate parts and yet also reassembled into a coherent, structured whole.

In a nutshell, evil can be expressed in many ways for Dostoevsky, but all these ways fall under the same paradigm, whose structure, I would argue, he himself suggests to us. Although subsequent philosophers were able to reframe the question of evil as a question of nihilism—in the inextricable link that he posited between freedom and nothingness—in order to work within this paradigm those who followed did not need to share the same beliefs and aims as the Russian writer, and even less his religious, Christian Orthodox leaning. Embarking on the path opened up by Demons, before defining any content, meant breaking with the strategies that had served philosophy up to that point. It meant, first, sealing off access to any sort of naïvely dualistic, metaphysical resubstantialization; and, second, opposing all possible versions of the Platonic schema of the nonexistence of evil. It meant rejecting both theological and philosophical theodicy. And most importantly, it meant leaving behind the strategies that modern rationality had tried to use to circumvent or neutralize this question. We could go so far as to summarize Shestov's thesis—for whom "the true Critique of Reason" was performed not by Immanuel Kant but by Fyodor Dostoevsky—with the claim that the genuine "radicality of evil" was conceived not in the arguments put forward in Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone but rather in the plot of Demons.


What Kant Dared Not Think About: Kant and Schelling

Perhaps it would be truer to say that Dostoevsky radicalized Kant's notion so far as to take Kant well beyond himself—or, rather, against himself. There is no doubt that, in the tortuous path along which philosophy attempted to think about evil, eventually restoring it to the freedom of the subject, the author of the Three Critiques marked a milestone.

Paul Ricoeur maintains that by naming evil, myths were the first instrument of symbolic and linguistic mediation to define and objectify the sense of a fear-inducing, confused, and speechless experience. If this is true, what sort of activity did philosophical reason perform? How did it go about leaving behind that primary, naïve sort of "spontaneous Manichaeism" that separates an experience of the good from an experience of evil by rigidly opposing them? The idea that Being is coextensive with the Good, thus relegating Evil to Non-Being, was introduced by Plato, as we know, and developed by Augustine. It proved to be the most tenacious response put forward by metaphysics: a relation of identity that would hold firm in the face of many lexical and conceptual changes. However, there is an obvious danger associated with deconstructing dualistic substantialism: such a powerful downplaying of evil can turn the force of the negative into something that exists purely to serve the positive. Poised perpetually on the brink of this double risk—of a "realist" dualism on the one hand, and of an idealist or historicist reductionism on the other—philosophy tenaciously sought to avert the danger at several key moments. It did so by resorting to a "revolutionary" force, so to speak: one that posits a close relationship between evil and freedom, going so far as to make evil the very condition of freedom. Except that, when faced with the "absurdity" of Being and God that such a prospect seemed to invite, on every occasion it retreated in fright to return to its ranks, as it were. This is the alternation that the question of evil continued to repeat, both in theology and metaphysics, until the end of the modern era. It oscillated constantly between dualism and its neutralization, between a vision of evil as a substance and a vision that denied its reality. Only occasionally did philosophy escape from this alternation, by arguing for a moral evil that implies an irreducible freedom.

In his own personal journey, Augustine seems to have foreseen how the possible future solutions would play out. As we know, in the battle against the Manichaeism of his past—against a temptation that was perhaps never completely put to rest—he accepted the legacy of Plotinus in order to give a sense to evil that was also logically consistent. Because thought about Being is equivalent to thought about the One—and therefore, to thought about the Good—evil cannot be a substance. In addition to this perspective, in Augustine there appeared a new notion of "nothingness"—the nothingness associated with creation ex nihilo that is connected to the idea of an absolute origin. This sets up negativity as a sign of the distance between creator and creature, and marks the ontological deficiency of creation as such. So alongside the belief that metaphysical evil is an error of the perspective from which human beings judge the world, due to our finitude, comes the idea that moral evil is the result of guilt, sin, or a perversion that deviates the upright will. Along with the Apostle Paul, Augustine knew that human beings have the ability to transgress or disturb the order of being. And he knew that once we are opened up to that order, when we participate in the reality of God, the fullness of our own being that we experience can only make the return to our normal state seem like a lack. This is the first sign that nothingness—out of which human beings were brought into being—leaves imprinted on the creature. Though the ontological approach of the privatio boni (the privation of good) and the moral approach of a subjective perspective were still logically indistinguishable at this point, in the modern era they began to gradually separate.

It was Kant who took the decisive step of restoring moral evil to human freedom. Under the blows to rational theology, which considered theodicy a "transcendental illusion," the Kantian critique laid down the first, foundational cornerstones for the deconstruction of onto-theology. From then on, it would be very difficult to go back to talking about evil in and of itself. The term had previously embraced a diverse set of phenomena and concepts—from natural disasters to suffering, from a metaphysical principle to individual death—but starting with Kant, moral evil achieved its own philosophical autonomy. As Richard Bernstein points out, Kant's thought created the schism that made it possible to begin distinguishing clearly between physical evil, metaphysical evil, and moral evil. Consequently, the problem ceased to be purely a theological and metaphysical concern, while the relevant question shifted from "Where does evil come from?" to "Why do we commit evil deeds?"

For some, Kant's "radical evil" was a step backward with respect to his critical perspectives, while for others it was a coherent and innovative development. Either way, the concept laid down the foundations for modern and postmetaphysical thought on the question. Ricoeur is right in suggesting that the problem of evil has always functioned as a theoretical device for reforming philosophical systems. In other words, philosophy has used the appearance of a new question about evil as a tool to undermine the coherence of the previous philosophical system, in a catand-mouse game of structuring and destructuring. However, with Kant there came about a decisive transformation: although both the concept of malum metaphysicum (metaphysical evil) and the idea of privatio boni negate personal responsibility and imputability, for him the doctrine of original sin also restricts exploration of the link between freedom and evil.


(Continues...)
Excerpted from New Demons by Simona Forti, Zakiya Hanafi. Copyright © 2012 Giangiacomo Feltrinelli Editore. Excerpted by permission of STANFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

Le informazioni nella sezione "Su questo libro" possono far riferimento a edizioni diverse di questo titolo.

Compra usato

Condizioni: molto buono
The book has been read, but is...
Visualizza questo articolo

EUR 10,43 per la spedizione da Regno Unito a Italia

Destinazione, tempi e costi

EUR 6,10 per la spedizione da Regno Unito a Italia

Destinazione, tempi e costi

Altre edizioni note dello stesso titolo

9780804786249: New Demons: Rethinking Power and Evil Today

Edizione in evidenza

ISBN 10:  0804786240 ISBN 13:  9780804786249
Casa editrice: Stanford Univ Pr, 2014
Rilegato

Risultati della ricerca per The New Demons: Rethinking Power and Evil Today

Foto dell'editore

Forti, Simona
Editore: Stanford University Press, 2014
ISBN 10: 080479295X ISBN 13: 9780804792950
Antico o usato Paperback

Da: WorldofBooks, Goring-By-Sea, WS, Regno Unito

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

Paperback. Condizione: Very Good. The book has been read, but is in excellent condition. Pages are intact and not marred by notes or highlighting. The spine remains undamaged. Codice articolo GOR012383404

Contatta il venditore

Compra usato

EUR 15,57
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 10,43
Da: Regno Unito a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: 1 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Foto dell'editore

Simona Forti
ISBN 10: 080479295X ISBN 13: 9780804792950
Nuovo PAP

Da: PBShop.store UK, Fairford, GLOS, Regno Unito

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

PAP. Condizione: New. New Book. Shipped from UK. Established seller since 2000. Codice articolo FW-9780804792950

Contatta il venditore

Compra nuovo

EUR 30,34
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 6,10
Da: Regno Unito a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: 15 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Immagini fornite dal venditore

Forti, Simona
ISBN 10: 080479295X ISBN 13: 9780804792950
Nuovo Paperback or Softback

Da: BargainBookStores, Grand Rapids, MI, U.S.A.

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

Paperback or Softback. Condizione: New. New Demons: Rethinking Power and Evil Today 1.21. Book. Codice articolo BBS-9780804792950

Contatta il venditore

Compra nuovo

EUR 26,03
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 11,59
Da: U.S.A. a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: 5 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Foto dell'editore

Simona Forti
Editore: Stanford University Press, 2014
ISBN 10: 080479295X ISBN 13: 9780804792950
Nuovo Brossura Prima edizione

Da: Kennys Bookshop and Art Galleries Ltd., Galway, GY, Irlanda

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

Condizione: New. 2014. 1st Edition. Paperback. . . . . . Codice articolo V9780804792950

Contatta il venditore

Compra nuovo

EUR 37,04
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 2,00
Da: Irlanda a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: Più di 20 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Immagini fornite dal venditore

Simona Forti
ISBN 10: 080479295X ISBN 13: 9780804792950
Nuovo Paperback

Da: Rarewaves USA, OSWEGO, IL, U.S.A.

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

Paperback. Condizione: New. As long as we care about suffering in the world, says political philosopher Simona Forti, we are compelled to inquire into the question of evil. But is the concept of evil still useful in a postmodern landscape where absolute values have been leveled and relativized by a historicist perspective? Given our current unwillingness to judge others, what signposts remain to guide our ethical behavior? Surveying the nineteenth- and twentieth-century Western philosophical debates on evil, Forti concludes that it is time to leave behind what she calls "the Dostoevsky paradigm": the dualistic vision of an omnipotent monster pitted against absolute, helpless victims. No longer capable of grasping the normalization of evil in today's world-whose structures of power have been transformed-this paradigm has exhausted its explanatory force. In its place, Forti offers a different genealogy of the relationship between evil and power, one that finally calls into question power's recurrent link to transgression. At the center of contemporary evil she posits the passive attitude towards rule-following, the need for normalcy, and the desire for obedience nurtured by our contemporary mass democracies. In our times, she contends, evil must be explored in tandem with our stubborn desire to stay alive at all costs as much as with our deep need for recognition: the new modern absolutes. A courageous book, New Demons extends an original, inspiring call to ethical living in a biopolitical age. Codice articolo LU-9780804792950

Contatta il venditore

Compra nuovo

EUR 36,32
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 3,43
Da: U.S.A. a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: Più di 20 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Immagini fornite dal venditore

Simona Forti
ISBN 10: 080479295X ISBN 13: 9780804792950
Nuovo Paperback

Da: Rarewaves USA United, OSWEGO, IL, U.S.A.

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

Paperback. Condizione: New. As long as we care about suffering in the world, says political philosopher Simona Forti, we are compelled to inquire into the question of evil. But is the concept of evil still useful in a postmodern landscape where absolute values have been leveled and relativized by a historicist perspective? Given our current unwillingness to judge others, what signposts remain to guide our ethical behavior? Surveying the nineteenth- and twentieth-century Western philosophical debates on evil, Forti concludes that it is time to leave behind what she calls "the Dostoevsky paradigm": the dualistic vision of an omnipotent monster pitted against absolute, helpless victims. No longer capable of grasping the normalization of evil in today's world-whose structures of power have been transformed-this paradigm has exhausted its explanatory force. In its place, Forti offers a different genealogy of the relationship between evil and power, one that finally calls into question power's recurrent link to transgression. At the center of contemporary evil she posits the passive attitude towards rule-following, the need for normalcy, and the desire for obedience nurtured by our contemporary mass democracies. In our times, she contends, evil must be explored in tandem with our stubborn desire to stay alive at all costs as much as with our deep need for recognition: the new modern absolutes. A courageous book, New Demons extends an original, inspiring call to ethical living in a biopolitical age. Codice articolo LU-9780804792950

Contatta il venditore

Compra nuovo

EUR 38,03
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 3,43
Da: U.S.A. a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: Più di 20 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Foto dell'editore

Simona Forti
Editore: Stanford University Press, 2014
ISBN 10: 080479295X ISBN 13: 9780804792950
Nuovo Paperback / softback

Da: THE SAINT BOOKSTORE, Southport, Regno Unito

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

Paperback / softback. Condizione: New. New copy - Usually dispatched within 4 working days. 640. Codice articolo B9780804792950

Contatta il venditore

Compra nuovo

EUR 31,27
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 11,14
Da: Regno Unito a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: Più di 20 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Foto dell'editore

Forti, Simona
Editore: Stanford University Press, 2014
ISBN 10: 080479295X ISBN 13: 9780804792950
Nuovo Brossura

Da: Ria Christie Collections, Uxbridge, Regno Unito

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

Condizione: New. In. Codice articolo ria9780804792950_new

Contatta il venditore

Compra nuovo

EUR 33,14
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 10,42
Da: Regno Unito a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: Più di 20 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Immagini fornite dal venditore

Simona Forti|Zakiya Hanafi
Editore: STANFORD UNIV PR, 2014
ISBN 10: 080479295X ISBN 13: 9780804792950
Nuovo Kartoniert / Broschiert

Da: moluna, Greven, Germania

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

Kartoniert / Broschiert. Condizione: New. The New Demons combines an original investigation of twentieth century philosophical debates on evil and a critical engagement with the latest research on power and biopolitics in order to offer a unique vision of our contemporary human condition. Codice articolo 595016632

Contatta il venditore

Compra nuovo

EUR 35,21
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 9,70
Da: Germania a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: Più di 20 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Immagini fornite dal venditore

Forti, Simona; Hanafi, Zakiya (TRN)
Editore: Stanford University Press, 2014
ISBN 10: 080479295X ISBN 13: 9780804792950
Nuovo Brossura

Da: GreatBookPrices, Columbia, MD, U.S.A.

Valutazione del venditore 5 su 5 stelle 5 stelle, Maggiori informazioni sulle valutazioni dei venditori

Condizione: New. Codice articolo 21599505-n

Contatta il venditore

Compra nuovo

EUR 28,43
Convertire valuta
Spese di spedizione: EUR 17,16
Da: U.S.A. a: Italia
Destinazione, tempi e costi

Quantità: Più di 20 disponibili

Aggiungi al carrello

Vedi altre 14 copie di questo libro

Vedi tutti i risultati per questo libro